Home | Community | Message Board


This site includes paid links. Please support our sponsors.


Welcome to the Shroomery Message Board! You are experiencing a small sample of what the site has to offer. Please login or register to post messages and view our exclusive members-only content. You'll gain access to additional forums, file attachments, board customizations, encrypted private messages, and much more!

Shop: Kraken Kratom Red Vein Kratom   North Spore North Spore Mushroom Grow Kits & Cultivation Supplies   Bridgetown Botanicals CBD Concentrates   Myyco.com Golden Teacher Liquid Culture For Sale   Original Sensible Seeds Autoflowering Cannabis Seeds   Unfolding Nature Unfolding Nature: Being in the Implicate Order   PhytoExtractum Buy Bali Kratom Powder   MagicBag.co All-In-One Bags That Don't Suck

Jump to first unread post Pages: 1
Invisiblesilversoul7
Chill the FuckOut!
 User Gallery

Registered: 10/10/02
Posts: 27,301
Loc: mndfreeze's puppet army
Limitations of Language
    #1687609 - 07/05/03 07:33 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Is anyone else frustrated with the inability of language to describe what they've experienced? I am, especially when it comes to my psychedelic experiences. I have experienced God, but have no way of describing it to someone else, especially someone who has never tripped before. I also have no way of knowing whether other psychonaughts have experienced what I've experienced because they can't put it into words that describe it vividly enough. I'm sorry if this has been posted before.


--------------------


"It is dangerous to be right when the government is wrong."--Voltaire

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
OfflineRhizoid
carbon unit
Male

Registered: 01/22/00
Posts: 1,739
Loc: Europe
Last seen: 1 month, 17 days
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1687684 - 07/05/03 08:43 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Absolutely, it's extremely frustrating. I find it very hard even to describe it to myself (I write down personal notes sometimes after trips).

It's like when a zombie tries to describe to another zombie what it feels like to be a solipsist. :tongue: 

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisibleBoppity604
Stranger
Registered: 10/19/01
Posts: 1,056
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: Rhizoid]
    #1687764 - 07/05/03 10:03 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Language is a funny beast.  We're trapped by our own limited knowledge of vocabulary.  But even people with great vocabulary might still have difficulty in relating concepts and metaphors in a speech to help others understand their point in the way it was meant to be understood.  I think that's one of the beautiful things about consciousness and being human. 

When you start finding friends and loved ones in your life with whom you can communicate to without words...but through mere eye contact and understanding of the experience we're relating...it's an incredible moment.  I think having mental continuums that coexist at the same frequency is another form of language.  Part of the beauty of getting to know your friends is learning how they view the world and handle their perceptions via the way they behave and react.  I'm sure we all have one friend or family member who we can say this about, "PERSON is a great guy/gal but she/he takes a little getting used to.  She/he can be very passionate about things, but underneath the front he/she is a cool and trustworthy person."

I have noticed that the more secure an individual is with him/herself as a complete person (their identity, their happiness, their passions) the more accepting of others they are as well as the more able to relate their viewpoints to different people.  Consciousness is indeed a great thing to have, don't you think?  :smile:

Love & Light,

Boppity

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
OfflineStrumpling
Neuronaut
Registered: 10/11/02
Posts: 7,571
Loc: Hyperspace
Last seen: 12 years, 10 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1687815 - 07/05/03 10:30 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

man I don't understand what you're trying to say.... there are some things language just can't express, and I guess this is one of them  :tongue: :tongue: :cool: :tongue: :grin:


--------------------
Insert an "I think" mentally in front of eveything I say that seems sketchy, because I certainly don't KNOW much. Also; feel free to yell at me.
In addition: SHPONGLE

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Offlinenubious
1up on the rest

Registered: 10/20/02
Posts: 534
Loc: Canada
Last seen: 1 year, 4 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: Strumpling]
    #1687907 - 07/05/03 11:41 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Boppity I hear you on the communication without words.. my buddy Ryan is like that.. we'll just look at each other and then one will get up to roll a joint or whatever..

Does anyone else think that mild telepathy has a play on how people react to one and other? I'm not say direct communication, but I've been noticing a lot lately that I'll think of something to say or something to do, but just keep my mouth shut, and then someone else in the conversation will say or do that thing? I don't know, but it's really trippy.


--------------------
No one knows the worth of innocence till he knows it is gone forever, and that money can't buy it back. Not the saint, but the sinner that repenteth, is he to whom the full length and breadth, and height and depth, of life's meaning is revealed. Good and evil loose all objective meaning and are seen as equally necessary and contrasting elements in the masterpiece that is the universe.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Anonymous

Re: Limitations of Language [Re: nubious]
    #1688041 - 07/05/03 01:14 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

I know exactly what you are saying! I rely a lot on body language to communicate with people, which is why I'm really touchy feely. Words always end up making people misunderstand one another.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Offlineatomikfunksoldier
T'was born oftrue in the yearof the cock!

Registered: 04/07/03
Posts: 1,500
Loc: a human-infested anthill
Last seen: 20 years, 6 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: LeViTY]
    #1688214 - 07/05/03 03:00 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

my opinion is, if you cant express it, then dont express it, trying to express it will only warp the idea. the unexpressable is best left unexpressed, there is a reason for that---- if something cannot be verbally expressed then it should be experienced first hand by all humanoids.


--------------------
enjoy the entertaining indentity i have constructed for you while you can.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
OfflineSole_Worthy
Stranger

Registered: 04/20/03
Posts: 463
Loc: over here
Last seen: 2 years, 5 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: atomikfunksoldier]
    #1688580 - 07/05/03 06:30 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

take the word "strange", im sure we all agree on its definition, but it means different things to all of us


--------------------
get it all together get like birds of a feather

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisibleShroomismM
Space Travellin
Male User Gallery
Folding@home Statistics
Registered: 02/13/00
Posts: 66,015
Loc: 9th Dimension Flag
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1689093 - 07/05/03 10:42 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Some things cannot be explained, but must be experienced. Take explaining what it is like to trip on lsd.. you can't. Must experience.


--------------------

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Invisibleivi
 User Gallery

Registered: 01/30/03
Posts: 9,089
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: Sole_Worthy]
    #1689095 - 07/05/03 10:43 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

I dont understand You.
You don't understand me.


--------------------

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
OfflineStrumpling
Neuronaut
Registered: 10/11/02
Posts: 7,571
Loc: Hyperspace
Last seen: 12 years, 10 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: ivi]
    #1689312 - 07/06/03 12:51 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

in my opinion, the current structures and uses of language give way to so many misunderstandings and so much confusion and frustration because every brain records wildly different information, including information on every word and how it fits into "social interaction." Unfortunately I don't see any way around this other than continuing to evolve current language in an attempt to convey mass amounts of very clear data with a minimal amount of psychological manipulation

lol something like that :wink: of course I'm no professor or anything so whatever


--------------------
Insert an "I think" mentally in front of eveything I say that seems sketchy, because I certainly don't KNOW much. Also; feel free to yell at me.
In addition: SHPONGLE

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Offlinemntlfngrs
The Art of Casterbation
Male User Gallery

Registered: 07/18/02
Posts: 3,937
Last seen: 5 years, 6 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1689313 - 07/06/03 12:51 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Quote:

silversoul7 said:
Is anyone else frustrated with the inability of language to describe what they've experienced? I am, especially when it comes to my psychedelic experiences. I have experienced God, but have no way of describing it to someone else, especially someone who has never tripped before. I also have no way of knowing whether other psychonaughts have experienced what I've experienced because they can't put it into words that describe it vividly enough. I'm sorry if this has been posted before.




See. Like I said in your other thead. You should read The Dancing Wu Li Masters. It discusses exactly this.


--------------------
Be all and you'll be to end all

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisibleZero7a1
Leaving YourWasteland

Registered: 10/23/02
Posts: 3,594
Loc: Passing Cloud
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1689390 - 07/06/03 01:49 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

very frustrated... i hate talking . i would rather just keep quiet... now maybe i see why those monks kept a vow of silence. maybe they didnt know why, maybe they did, im starting to think i could see why they would. What is telepathy? your brain just thinks that cause my mouth moves that is something physical... well so are the electrical signals that make my mouth move to speak. but language.... people can attach whatever they want to what they say. I like pictures.... if a picture is worth a thousand words... shit. i would love to just sit down and beam some controlled pictures into some peoples heads. it might make things a lot easier... maybe a lot harder too.

i liked the article at www.deoxy.org about the need for the death of symbolism. how symbols have caused so much trouble.

i like action.... and people. and looking at things. talking about them, bullshitting about what they could be. SPEAKING about them. FUCKKKKK I WANT TO SEE THEM. With my eyes. We could sit here and debate about something all day, i wouldnt give a shit, not till i could see it. with my eyes, even if i couldnt "see" it, i could still look next to my challanger and gaze into the vast beyond and imagine. calculate. petty cybernetic talk.

So many great people here, most of which i will probably never meet. anonymous faces, with an out pour of ideas. sometimes i feel cheated, depleted by a failing system. language still doesnt cut it, unless you know how to do it. unless you can put thoughts and pictures in someones head like the flow of poetic verse. it seems that there wont be any "essence" and therefore no true gain on anything "here".

my grandfather said something to this effect: that you can work it out on paper, but until its actually together, manifested in 3d it doesnt mean shit.

i want to scream, i want a sculpture to walk and mesmerize the carelless individuals... RAHHHHHHHHHHHHHHH!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!




--------------------
What?

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisibleMyInsanityTrip
Stranger

Registered: 03/10/03
Posts: 2,218
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1689411 - 07/06/03 02:06 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Kind of long,a bit off-topic maybe, but a decent read.
-------------
Magic Words: How Language Augments Human Computation

Andy Clark

Philosophy/Neuroscience/Psychology Program
Department of Philosophy
Washington University
St. Louis, MO 63130

e-mail: andy@twinearth.wustl.edu





Abstract.
Public language, I argue, is a cognition-enhancing tool -- it is a species of external artifact whose current adaptive value is partially constituted by its role in re-shaping the kinds of computational space that our biological brains must negotiate in order to solve certain types of problems, or to carry out certain complex projects. This computational role of language has been somewhat neglected (not un-noticed, but not rigorously pursued either) in recent cognitive science, due perhaps to a (quite proper) fascination with and concentration upon, that other obvious dimension: the role of language as an instrument of interpersonal communication. In this chapter, I try to display the broad shape of the alternative orientation. I discuss the views of some recent (and not-so-recent) authors, who recognize in various ways, the potential role of language and text in transforming, reshaping and simplifying the computational tasks that confront the biological brain. I then pursue this idea through a series of examples involving planning, concept learning, the construction of complex thoughts and the capacity to refelect on our own cognitive profiles.




0. Word Power.
Of course, words aren't magic. Neither are sextants, compasses, maps, slide rules and all the other paraphenelia which have accreted around the basic biological brains of homo sapiens. In the case of these other tools and props, however, it is transparently clear that they function so as to either carry out or to facilitate computational operations important to various human projects. The slide rule transforms complex mathematical problems (ones that would baffle or tax the unaided subject) into simple tasks of perceptual recognition. The map provides geographical information in a format well-suited to aid complex planning and strategic military operations. The compass gathers and displays a kind of information that (most) unaided human subjects do not seem to command. These various tools and props thus act to generate information, or to store it, or to transform it, or some combination of the three. In so doing, they impact our individual and collective problem-solving capacities in much the same dramatic ways as various software packages impact the performance of a simple pc.

Public language, I shall argue, is just such a tool -- it is a species of external artifact whose current adaptive value is partially constituted by its role in re-shaping the kinds of computational space that our biological brains must negotiate in order to solve certain types of problems, or to carry out certain complex projects. This computational role of language has been somewhat neglected (not un-noticed, but not rigorously pursued either) in recent cognitive science, due perhaps to a (quite proper) fascination with and concentration upon, that other obvious dimension: the role of language as an instrument of interpersonal communication. Work on sentence parsing, language use and story understanding has thus concentrated on the role of language in processes of information transfer between agents and on information retrieval from texts. But it has had little to say about the computational role of the linguistic formulations themselves, or about the special properties of the external media that support linguistic encodings.

In this chapter, I hope to display the broad shape of such an alternative interest. I begin by discussing the views of some recent (and not-so-recent) authors, who recognize in various ways, the potential role of language and text in transforming, reshaping and simplifying the computational tasks that confront the biological brain.Sections 2 and 3 pursue this broad vision across a variety of cases involving planning, coordination, learning and the construction of complex thoughts and arguments. The fourth section extends these last considerations to encompass the rather special class of meta-cognitive operations and tries to implicate language as an essential part of the process of thinking about our own thoughts and cognitive profiles. The final section suggests some broader implications and raises some questions concerning the boundary between the intelligent agent and the world.




1. Supra-Communicative Views of Language .
The idea that language may do far more than merely serve as a vehicle for communication is not new. It is clearly present in the work of developmentalists such as Vygotsky (1962), and more recently that of Laura Berk and others (see e.g. essays in Diaz and Berk (1992)). It figures in the philosophical conjectures and arguments of e.g. Peter Carruthers (to appear) and Ray Jackendoff (to appear). And it surfaces in the more cognitive science oriented speculations of Daniel Dennett (1991). It will be helpful to begin by rehearsing some of the central ideas in this literature, before pursuing our own version viz. the idea of language as a computational transformer which allows pattern-completing brains to tackle otherwise intractable classes of cognitive problems.

Lev Vygotsky, a Soviet psychologist of the 1930's, pioneered the idea that the use of public language had profound effects on cognitive development. He posited powerful links between speech, social experience and learning. Two especially pertinent Vygotskian ideas, for present purposes, concern the role of private speech, and of scaffolded action (action within the so-called zone of proximal development -- see Vygotsky (trans., 1962)). We may call an action `scaffolded' to the extent that it relies on some kind of external support. Such support could come from the use of tools, or the knowledge and skills of others; that is to say, scaffolding (as I shall use the term) denotes a broad class of physical, cognitive and social augmentations -- augmentations which allow us to achieve some goal which would otherwise be beyond us. Simple examples include the use of a compass and pencil to draw a perfect circle, the role of other crew members in enabling a ship's pilot to steer a course and the infants ability to take its first steps only while suspended in the enabling grip of its parents. Vygotsky's focus on what was termed the Zone of Proximal Development was concerned with this latter type of case, in which a child is temporarily able to succeed at designated tasks only by courtesy of the guidance or help provided by another human being (usually, a parent or teacher). This idea dovetails with Vygotsky's interest in private speech in the following way. When the child, confronted by a tricky challenge, is `talked through' the problem by a more experienced agent, the child can often succeed at tasks which would otherwise prove impossible (think of learning to tie your shoelaces). Later on, when the adult is absent, the child can conduct a similar dialogue, but this time with herself. But even in this latter case, it is argued, the speech (be it vocal or `internalized') functions so as to guide behavior, to focus attention, and to guard against common errors. In such cases, the role of language is to guide and shape our own behavior -- it is a tool for structuring and controlling action and not merely a medium of information transfer between agents.

This Vygotskian image is supported by more recent bodies of developmental research, such as that carried out by Laura Berk and Ruth Garvin. Berk and Garvin (1984) observed and recorded the ongoing speech of a group of 5-10 year olds in Kentucky. They found that most of the children's private speech (speech not addressed to some other listener) seemed keyed to the direction and control of the child's own actions. They found that the incidence of such speech increased when the child was alone and engaged in trying to perform some difficult task. In subsequent studies (Bivens and Berk (1990), Berk (1994)) it was found that the children who made the most self-directed comments were the ones who subsequently mastered the tasks best. Berk's conclusions, from these and other studies, was that self-directed speech (be it vocal or silent inner rehearsal) is a crucial cognitive tool that allows us to highlight the most puzzling features of new situations, and to direct and control our own problem-solving actions.

The theme of language as a tool has also been developed by the philosopher Christopher Gauker. Gauker's concern, however, is to re-think the intra-individual role of language in terms of (what he calls) a `cause-effect analysis'. The idea here is to depict public language "not as a tool for representing the world or expressing ones thoughts but a tool for effecting changes in one's environment" (Gauker (1990) p. 31). To get the flavor, consider the use of a symbol, by a chimpanzee, to request a banana. The chimp touches a specific key on a key-pad (the precise physical location of the key can be varied between trials) and learns that making that symbol light tends to promote the arrival of bananas. The chimp's quasi-linguistic understanding is explicable Gauker suggests, in terms of the chimp's appreciation of a cause-effect relationship between the symbol production and changes in its local environment. Gauker looks at a variety of symbol-using behaviors and concludes that they all succumb to this kind of analysis. This leads him to hypothesize that, although clearly more complex, human beings' linguistic understanding likewise "consists in a grasp of the causal relations into which linguistic signs may enter" (Gauker, op.cit., 44).

Gauker tends to see the role of language as, if you like, directly causal: as a way of getting things done, much like reaching out your hand and grabbing a cake. However, the idea that we learn, by experience, of the peculiar causal potencies of specific signs and symbols is in principle much broader. We might even, as in the Vygotskian examples and as argued in Dennett (1991), discover that the self-directed utterance of words and phrases has certain effects on our own behavior! We might also learn to exploit language as a tool in a variety of even less direct ways, as a means of altering the shape of computational problem spaces (see Section 2 following).

One obvious question which the putative role of language as a self-directed tool raises is "how does it work?". What is it about, for example, self-directed speech which fits it to play a guiding role? After all, it is not at all clear how we can tell ourselves anything we don't already know! Surely, all that public language can ever be is a medium for expressing ideas which are already formulated and understood in some other, more basic, inner code? It is precisely this view which a supra-communicative account of language has ultimately to reject.

One way to do so is to depict public language as itself the medium of a special kind of thought. Another (not altogether distinct) way is to depict linguaform inputs as having distinctive effects on some inner computational device. Peter Carruthers{1} (to appear) champions the first of these, while Daniel Dennett (1991) offers a version of the second. Thus Carruthers argues that, in this case at least, we should take very seriously the evidence of our own introspection. It certainly often seems as if our very thoughts are composed of the words and sentences of public language. And the reason we have this impression, Carruthers argues, is because it is true: "inner thinking is literally done in inner speech (see Carruthers (to appear) ch. 2 for an extensive discussion). By extension, Carruthers is able to view many intra-personal uses of language as less a matter of simple communication than of (what he nicely terms) public thinking. This perspective fits satisfyingly with the Vygotskian view championed by Berk, and is also applicable to the interesting case of writing down our ideas. Here Carruthers suggests "one does not first entertain a private thought and then write it down: rather, the thinking is the writing" (Carruthers, to appear, MS p. 56). I shall return to this point later (see section 2), since I believe that what Carruthers says is almost right, but that we can better understand the kind of case he has in mind by treating the writing as an environmental manipulation which transforms the problem space for human brains.

Carruthers, in depicting language as itself the vehicle of (certain types of) thought, is nonetheless careful to reject what he calls the `Whorfian Relativism of the Standard Social Science Model' (op.cit., MS p. 302). The reference here is to the idea, promoted by Benjamin Whorf (1956), that human minds are profoundly shaped and altered by the particular public languages we come to speak. Carruthers view is not that specific languages somehow deeply alter or re-program the brain, but rather{2} that certain kinds of human thinking are actually constituted by sequences of public language symbols (written down, spoken, or internally imagined). Such a hypothesis, Carruthers argues, can help account for a wide range of both introspective and experimental and pathological data{3}.

An alternative way to unpack a supra-communicative view of language, we noted, is to suppose that the linguistic inputs actually re-program or otherwise alter the high-level computational structure of the brain itself. The exegesis is delicate (and therefore tentative), but something akin to this view seems to be held by Daniel Dennett when he suggests that "conscious human minds are more-or-less serial virtual machines implemented-inefficiently-on the parallel hardware that evolution has provided for us" (Dennett, 1991, p. 278). In this and other passages, the idea seems to be that the bombardment of (something like) parallel processing, connectionist, pattern-completing brains by (amongst other things) public language texts and sentences (reminders, plans, exhortations, questions, etc.), results in a kind of cognitive reorganization akin to that which occurs when one computer system simulates another. In such cases, the installation of a new program allows the user to treat e.g. a serial LISP machine as if it was a massively parallel connectionist device. What Dennett is proposing is, he tells us (op.cit., p.218) the same trick in reverse viz. the simulation of something like a serial logic engine using the altogether different resources of the massively parallel neural networks which biological evolution rightly favors for real-world, real-time survival and action.

Strikingly, Dennett suggests that it is this subtle re-programming of the brain by (primarily) linguistic bombardment which yields the phenomena of human consciousness (our sense of self) and enables us to far surpass the behavioral and cognitive achievements of most other animals (see e.g. Dennett (1995) p. 370-373). Dennett thus depicts our advanced cognitive skills as in large part a result not of our innate hardware (which may differ only in small, though important, ways from that of other animals) but of the special way that various plastic (programmable) features of the brain are modified by the effects of culture and language. As Dennett puts it, the serial machine is installed courtesy of "myriad microsettings in the plasticity of the brain" (Dennett (1991) p. 219). Of course, mere exposure to culture and language is not sufficient to ensure human-like cognition. You can expose a cockroach to all the language you like and get no trace of the cognitive transformations which Dennett sees in us. Dennett's claim is not that there are no initial hardware level differences. Rather it is that some relatively small hardware differences (e.g. between us and a chimpanzee) allow us to both create and benefit from public language and other cultural developments in ways which lead to a great snowball of cognitive change and augmentation, including, crucially, the literal installation of a new kind of computational device inside the brain.

Dennett's vision is complex, and not altogether unambiguous. The view I want to develop is clearly deeply related, but differs (I think) in one crucial respect. Where Dennett sees public language as effecting a profound but subtle re-organization of the brain itself, I am inclined to see it as in essence heart an external resource which complements -- but does not profoundly alter -- the brains own basic modes of representation and computation. That is to say, I see the changes as relatively superficial ones, geared to allowing us to use and exploit various external resource to the full. The positions are not, of course, wholly distinct. (Indeed, Dennett now suggests (personal communication) that his view is rather that exposure to language leads to a variety of relatively superficial changes at the neural/computational level, but that these changes nonetheless amount to something close to the inner implementation of a system of moveable symbols. The sense in which we may come to implement a classical virtual machine is thus stronger than any mere input-output level similarity, yet weaker than the kind of fine-grained simulation of an alternative computational architecture found in eg Touretsky's connectionist implementation of a production system.). In any case, the mere fact that we often mentally rehearse sentences in our head and use them to guide and alter our behavior means that one cannot (and should not) treat language and culture as wholly external resources. Nonetheless, it remains possible that such rehearsal neither requires nor results in the installation of any fundamentally different kind of computational device in the brain, but rather involves the use of the same old (essentially pattern-completing) resources to model the special kinds of behavior observed in the public linguistic world. And as Paul Churchland (1995, p. 264-269) points out, there is indeed a class of connectionist networks (`recurrent networks' -- see Elman (1993), and further discussion in Clark (1993)) which do seem well-suited to modeling such behavior.

This view of inner rehearsal is nicely developed by the connectionists Rumelhart, Smolensky, McClelland, and Hinton who argue that the general strategy of "mentally modeling" the behavior of selected aspects of our environment is especially important insofar as it allows us to imagine external resources with which we have previously physically interacted, and to replay the dynamics of such interactions in our heads. Thus experience with drawing and using Venn diagrams allows us to train a neural network which subsequently allows us to manipulate imagined Venn diagrams in our heads. Such imaginative manipulations require a specially trained neural resource to be sure. But there is no reason to suppose that such training results in the installation of a different kind of computational device. It is the same old process of pattern completion in high dimensional representational spaces, but applied to the special domain of a specific kind of external representation, The link to a Vygotskian image is clear and remarked upon by the authors who the summarize their view saying:

We can be instructed to behave in a particular way. Responding to instructions in this way can be viewed simply as responding to some environmental event. We can also remember such an instruction and "tell ourselves" what to do. We have, in this way, internalized the instruction. We believe that the process of following instructions is essentially the same whether we have told ourselves or have been told what to do. Thus even here we have a kind of internalization of an external representational format.

(Rumelhart, Smolensky, McClelland, and Hinton (1986) p.47)

The larger passage (p. 44-48) from which the above is extracted is, in fact, remarkably rich and touches on several of our major themes. The authors note that such external formalisms are especially hard to invent and slow to develop, and are themselves the kinds of product which (in an innocently bootstrapping kind of way) can evolve only thanks to the linguistically-mediated processes of cultural storage and gradual refinement over many lifetimes. They also note that by using real external representations we put ourselves in a position to use our basic perceptual/motor skills to separate problems into parts and to attend to a series of sub-problems, storing intermediate results along the way.

The Rumelhart et al vision thus depicts language as a key element in a variety of environmentally extended computational processes. This notion of computational processes inhering in larger systems (ones that may incorporate the activities of many individual biological brains) is further developed and defended in Hutchins (1995). Hutchins offers a beautiful and detailed treatment that highlights the ways representation may flow and be transformed within larger, socially and technologically extended systems. Hutchins' main example involves the way maps, instruments, texts and vocalizations all contribute to the complex process of ship navigation: a process that is best analyzed as an extended sequence of computational transitions, many of whose role is to transform problems into formats better situated to the perceptual and pattern-completing capacities of biological brains. The environmental operations thus complement the activities of the biological brains.

The tack I am about to pursue likewise depicts language as an external artifact designed to complement, rather than recapitulate or transfigure, the basic processing profile we share with other animals. It does not depict experience with language as a source of profound inner re-programming (pac? Dennett). Whether it depicts inner linguistic rehearsal as literally constitutive of specific human cognizings (as Carruthers claims) is moot. Certainly, inner rehearsals, when they occur, are quite literally models of linguistic productions. But what is most important, I believe, is not to try to answer the question, "do we actually think in words" (to which the answer is "in a way yes, in a way no"!) but to try to see what computational benefits accrue to biological pattern-completing brains in virtue of their ability to manipulate and sometimes model external representational artifacts.




2. Language and Computation: The 6 Ways.

Here, then, are six broad ways in which linguistic artifacts can complement the activity of the pattern-completing brain.


i. Memory Augmentation.

This is, of course, the most obvious and oft-remarked case. Here we simply use the artifactual world of texts, diaries, notebooks and the like as a means of systematically storing large and often complex bodies of data. We may also use simple external manipulations (such as leaving a note on the mirror) to prompt the recall, from on-board biological memory, of appropriate information and intentions at the right time. Here, the use of linguistic artifacts is perfectly continuous with a variety of other, simpler, environmental manipulations, such as leaving the empty olive oil bottle by the door so that you cannot help but run across it (and hence recall the need for olive oil) as you set out for the shops.


ii. Environmental Simplification.

This has both an obvious and a not-so-obvious aspect. The obvious (but still important) aspect concerns the use of labels to provide perceptually simple clues to help us negotiate complex environments. Signs for the cloakrooms, for nightclubs, and for city centers all fulfill this role. They allow a little learning to go a very long way, helping you find your targets in new cities without knowing in advance what, in detail, to seek or even where exactly to seek it. McClamrock (1995 p. 88) describes this strategy as one in which we "enforce on the environment certain kinds of stable properties that will lessen our computational burdens and the demands on us for inference."

Closely related, but much less obvious, is the provision, by the use of linguistic labels, of a greatly simplified learning environment. It can be shown, for example, that the provision of linguistic labels for classes of perceptually presented objects can speed category learning in artificial neural networks. This is because the presentation of the same label accompanying a series of slightly different perceptual inputs (e.g., different views of dogs) gives the network a heavy hint. It flags the presence of some further underlying structure and thus invites the network to seek the perceptual commonality (for a detailed discussion see Schyns (1991), Clark (1993) Ch. 5). It also seems likely (though no formal demonstration exists) that for certain very abstract concepts, the only route to successful learning may go via the provision of linguistic glosses. Concept such as charity, extortion and black hole seem pitched too far from perceptual facts to be learnable without exposure to linguistically formulated theories. Language may thus enable us to comprehend equivalence classes that would otherwise lie forever outside our intellectual horizons.



iii. Coordination and the Reduction of On-Line Deliberation.

Human beings often make explicit plans. We say to others that we will be at such and such a place at such and such a time. We even play this game with ourselves, perhaps by writing down a list of what we will do on what days and so on. Superficially, the role of such explicit planning is to allow the coordination of actions. Thus, if the other person knows you have said you'll be at the station at 9:00 a.m., they can time their taxi accordingly. Or, in the solo case, if you have to buy the paint before touching up the car, and if you have to go to the shops to buy other items anyway, you can minimize your efforts and enforce proper sequencing by following a plan. As the space of demands and opportunities grows, it often becomes necessary to use pencil and paper to organize and to re-organize the options, and then to preserve the result as a kind of external control structure available to guide your subsequent actions.

Closely related to such coordinative functions is the function of oiling the wheels of collaborative problem-solving. Collaborative problem solving (see e.g., Tomasello et al (1993) involves much more than the mere exchange of information and orchestration of activity. It involves actively prompting the other to work harder at certain aspects of a problem, and allowing the other to focus your own attention in places you might otherwise ignore. Here, then, the co-ordinative function of linguistic exchange phases into the further one of manipulating attention and controlling resource allocation (see (v) below).

Such broadly co-ordinative functions, thought important, do not exhaust the benefits of explicit (usually language-based) planning. As Michael Bratman has recently pointed out, the creation of explicit plans may play a special role in reducing the on-line cognitive load on resource-limited agents like ourselves. The idea here is that our plans have a kind of stability which pays dividends by reducing the amount of deliberation in which we engage as we go about much of our daily business. Of course, new information can, and often does, cause us to revise our plans. But we do not let every slight change prompt a re-assessment of our plans, intentions, even when other things being equal, we might now choose slightly differently. Human plans and intentions, Bratman suggests, play the role of blocking a wasteful process of continual re-assessment and choice, except in cases where there is some quite major pay-off for the disruption. (See Bratman (1987) for a full discussion).

Linguistic exchange and formulation thus plays a key role in coordinating activities (both at an inter- and intra-personal level) and in reducing the amount of daily on-line deliberation in which we engage.



iv. Taming Path-Dependent Learning.

Human learning, like learning in Artificial Neural Networks, looks hostage to at least some degree of path dependency. Certain ideas can be understood only once others are in place. The training received by one mind fits it to grasp and expand upon ideas which gain no foothold of comprehension in another. The processes of formal education, indeed, are geared to take young (and not so young) minds along a genuine intellectual journey, which may involve beginning with ideas now known to be incorrect, but which alone seem able to prime the system to later appreciate a finer grained truth. Such mundane facts are a reflection of cognitive path dependence -- you can't get everywhere from anywhere; where you are now strongly constrains your future intellectual trajectory. Moreover, such path dependency is nicely explained (see e.g., Elman (1993)) by treating intellectual progress as involving something like a process of computational search in a large and complex space. Previous learning inclines the system to try out certain locations in the space and not others. When the prior learning is appropriate, the job of learning some new regularity is made tractable: the prior learning acts as a filter on the space of options to be explored. Artificial Neural Networks which employ gradient descent learning methods are highly constrained insofar as the learning routine forces the network always to explore at the edges of its current weight assignments. Since these constitute its current knowledge, it means that such networks cannot `jump around' in hypothesis space. The networks current location in weight space (its current knowledge) is thus a major constraint on what new `ideas' it can next explore (see Elman (1993) p.94).

When confronting devices which exhibit some degree of path dependency, the mundane observation that language allows ideas to be preserved and to migrate between individuals takes on a new force. For we can now appreciate how such migrations may allow the communal construction of extremely delicate and difficult intellectual trajectories and progressions. An idea which only Joe's prior experience could make available, but which can flourish only in the intellectual niche currently provided by the brain of Mary, can now realize its full potential by journeying between agents as and when required. Moreover, the sheer number of intellectual niches available within a linguistically linked community provides a stunning matrix of possible inter-agent trajectories. The observation that public language allows human cognition to be collective (e.g. Churchland (1995) p. 270) takes on new depth once we recognize the role of such collective endeavor in transcending the path-dependent nature of individual human cognition.



v. Attention and Resource Allocation.

Ron McClamrock reports a nice case from Marr{4} in which we see a control loop which runs outside the head and into the local environment, In McClamrock's words:

Flies, it turns out, don't quite know that to fly they should flap their wings. They don't take off by sending some signal from the brain to the wings. Rather, there is a direct control link from the fly's feet to its wings, such that when the feet cease to be in contact with a surface, the fly's wings begin to flap. To take off, the fly simply jumps and then lets the signal from the feet trigger the wings.

(McClamrock (1995) p. 85; emphasis in original.)

Notice, then, how written and spoken language at times serves a similar goal. We write down a note to do such and such, thus creating an externalized control loop for our own future behavior. We follow someones vocal instructions as we learn to windsurf. Or we mentally rehearse such instruction as we practice on our own. Such phenomena reveal linguistic formulations as somehow helping to focus, monitor and control behavior. I do not think we yet understand exactly how language (especially mental rehearsal of instructions) interacts with more basic on-line resources so as to yield these benefits. But that it does indeed play some such role seems clear.


vi. Data Manipulation and Representation.

This final benefit accrues most directly to the use of actual text. As I construct this chapter, for example, I am continually creating, putting aside, and re-organizing chunks of text. I have a file which contains all kinds of hints and fragments, stored up over a long period of time, which may be germane to the discussion. I have source texts and papers full of notes and annotations. As I (literally, physically) move these things about, interacting first with one, then another, making new notes, annotations and plans, so the intellectual shape of the chapter grows and solidifies. It is a shape which does not spring fully developed from inner cogitations. Instead, it is the product of a sustained and iterated sequence of interactions between my brain and a variety of external props. In these cases, I am willing to say, a good deal of actual thinking involves loops and circuits which run outside the head and through the local environment. Extended intellectual arguments and theses are almost always the product of brains acting in concert with multiple external resources. These resources enable us to pursue manipulations and juxtapositions of ideas and data which would quickly baffle the un-augmented brain. (The simple case of physically manipulating Scrabble tiles to present new potential word-fragments to a pattern-completing brain (see Kirsh (to appear)) is a micro-version of the same strategy). In all such cases, the real environment of printed words and symbols allows us to search, store, sequence and reorganize data in ways alien to the on-board repertoire of the biological brain.

The moral of the 6 ways is thus clear. The role of public language and text in human cognition is not limited to the preservation and communication of ideas. Instead, these external resources make available concepts, strategies and learning trajectories which are simply not available to individual, un-augmented brains. Much of the true power of language lies in its underappreciated capacity to re-shape the computational spaces which confront intelligent agents.





3. Words as Filters
The "six ways" pursued in the previous section revolve around two broad, and rather distinct, themes. One is the use of text and/or speech as forms of external memory and workspace. The other is the (putative) role of words and sentences (preserved and transmitted through the medium of public language) to act as transformers of the very shape of the cognitive and computational spaces we inhabit. This second theme, it seems to me, is the more generally neglected of the two, and so it may be worth expanding on it a little further.

Consider the idea of words as filters on the search space for a biological learning device. The idea here ( a kind of corollary of some of Elman's ideas as rehearsed in the previous section) is that learning to associate concepts with discrete arbitrary labels (words) somehow makes it easier to use those concepts to constrain computational search and hence enables the acquisition of a cascade of more complex and increasingly abstract ideas. The claim (see also Clark and Thornton (in press)) is thus that associating a perceptually simple, stable, external item (such as a word) with an idea, concept or piece of knowledge effectively freezes the concept into a sort of cognitive building block- an item that can then be treated as a simple baseline feature for future episodes of thought, learning and search.

This broad conjecture (whose statistical and computational foundations are explored in the co-authored piece mentioned above) seems to be supported by some recent work on chimp cognition. Thompson, Oden and Boyson (in press) is a study of problem solving in pan troglodytes and concerns the abilities of the chimps solve puzzles that require matching relations-between-relations. Merely matching (first order) relations might involve e.g. training the chimps to match the identical items (such as two identical cups ) in an array. Matching relations-between-relations, by contrast, involves e.g. getting the chimps to match pairs of identical items (e.g. two identical shoes) to other pairs of (different) identical items (such as two identical cups). And conversely, matching pairs of different items (e.g. a cup and a shoe) to other pairs of different items (e.g. a pen a and a padlock). The higher order task is thus not to match the items themselves but to match the relations that obtain between hem- it is to match the pairs in terms of the relational properties they exhibit irrespective of the specific items involved.

What makes the higher order task higher order, it should be clear, is that there is an additional step of reasoning involved. The chimps must first represent the two (within pair) items as being the same, and then match the pairs of pairs according to whether or not each member of the pair of pairs exhibits the same relational property (sameness or difference). Now it is well known ( see e.g. the review in Thompson and Oden (1996)) that non-language trained infant chimps can perceptually detect the basic relations of similarity and difference, but that they cannot make the higher-order judgments pairing instantiations of the relations themselves.It is also well-known (though highly illuminating) that language trained chimps CAN learn to perform this higher order task. These are chimps who have learnt to use symbols for 'same' and 'different' and have, in addition, attained some degree of minimal syntactic competence such as the ability to compose proto-sentences (see e.g. Premack and Premack 1993). What Thompson et al nicely go on to demonstrate is that (pace Premack and Premack) what is responsible for this 'cognitive bonus' is not syntactic competence per se but simply the experience of associating abstract relations with arbitrary tokens. Thus chimps with no compositional linguistic training but with a history of rewards for associating e.g. a plastic heart token with the presentation of pairs exhibiting sameness and a diagonal token with the presentation of pairs exhibiting difference are shown to learn the higher order matching task as easily as the others. Chimps with no history of associating the relations with external tokens (predictably) fail to perform the higher-order task.

Naturally, such experiments involve in addition a whole host of careful controls and important experimental details. I here refer the reader to the detailed study in Thompson et al (in press) and the background review in Thompson and Oden (1996). The author's conclusions, however, bear repeating. They conclude that (in this case at least) it is the use of simple, arbitrary external tags for independently identifiable relational properties that opens up the more abstract space of knowledge about relations between relations. This fits perfectly with Dennett's (1994) suspicion that it is the practice of tagging and labeling itself, rather that full-blooded syntactic competence per se, that may have been the crucial innovation that opened u new cognitive horizons to proto-language using creatures. Learning such a set of tags and labels (which we all do when w e learn a language) is, I would speculate, rather closely akin to acquiring a new perceptual modality. For

like a perceptual modality, it renders certain features of our world concrete and salient, and allows us to target our thoughts (and learning algorithms) on a new domain of basic objects. This new domain compresses what were previously complex and unruly sensory patterns into simple objects. These simple objects can then be attended to in ways that quickly reveal further (otherwise hidden) patterns, as in the case of relations-between-relations. And of course the whole process is deeply iterative- we coin new words and labels to concretize regularities that we could only originally conceptualize thanks to a backdrop of other words and labels. The most powerful and familiar incarnation of this iterative strategy is, perhaps, the edifice of human science.





4. Mangroves and Meta-Cognition.
If a tree is seen growing on an island, which do you suppose came first? It is natural (and usually correct) to assume that the island provided the fertile soil in which a lucky seed came to rest. Mangrove forests,{5} however, constitute a revealing exception to this general rule. The Mangrove grows from a floating seed which establishes itself in the water, rooting in shallow mud flats. The seedling sends complex vertical roots through the surface of the water, culminating in what looks to all intents and purposes like a small tree posing on stilts. The complex system of aerial roots, however, soon traps floating soil, weed and debris. After a time, the accumulation of trapped matter forms a small island. As more time passes, the island grows larger and larger. A growing mass of such islands can eventually merge, effectively extending the shoreline out to the trees! Throughout this process, and despite our prior intuitions, it is the land which is progressively built by the trees.

Something like the Mangrove effect, I suspect, is operative in some species of human thought. It is natural to suppose that words are always rooted in the fertile soil of pre-existing thoughts. But sometimes, at least, the influence seems to run in the other direction. A simple example is poetry. In constructing a poem, we do not simply use words to express thoughts. Rather, it is often the properties which of the words (their structure and cadence) which determine the thoughts that the poem comes to express. A similar partial reversal can occur during the construction of complex texts and arguments. By writing down our ideas we generate a trace in a format which opens up a range of new possibilities. We can then inspect and re-inspect the same ideas, coming at them from many different angles and in many different frames of mind. We can hold the original ideas steady so that we may judge them, and safely experiment with subtle alterations. We can store them in ways which allow us to compare and combine them with other complexes of ideas in ways which would quickly defeat the un-augmented imagination. In these ways, and as remarked in the previous section, the real properties of physical text transform the space of possible thoughts.

Such observations lead me to the following conjecture. Perhaps it is public language which is responsible for a complex of rather distinctive features of human thought viz, our ability to display second order cognitive dynamics. By second order cognitive dynamics I mean a cluster of powerful capacities involving self-evaluation, self-criticism and finely honed remedial responses.{6} Examples would include: recognizing a flaw in our own plan or argument, and dedicating further cognitive efforts to fixing it; reflecting on the unreliability of our own initial judgements in certain types of situations and proceeding with special caution as a result; coming to see why we reached a particular conclusion by appreciating the logical transitions in our own thought; thinking about the conditions under which we think best and trying to bring them about. The list could be continued, but the patten should be clear. In all these cases, we are effectively thinking about our own cognitive profiles or about specific thoughts. This "thinking about thinking", is a good candidate for a distinctively human capacity -- one not evidently shared by the other, non-language-using animals who share our planet. As such, it is natural to wonder whether this might be an entire species of thought in which language plays the generative role -- a species of thought which is not just reflected in, or extended by, our use of words but is directly dependent upon language for its very existence. Public language and the inner rehearsal of sentences would, on this model, act like the aerial roots of the Mangrove tree -- the words would serve as fixed points capable of attracting and positioning additional intellectual matter, creating the islands of second-order thought so characteristic of the cognitive landscape of homo sapiens.

It is easy to see, in broad outline, how this might come about. For as soon as we formulate a thought in words (or on paper), it becomes an object for both ourselves and for others. As an object, it is the kind of thing we can have thoughts about. In creating the object, we need have no thoughts about thoughts -- but once it is there, the opportunity immediately exists to attend to it as an object in its own right. The process of linguistic formulation thus creates the stable structure to which subsequent thinkings attach.

Just such a twist on potential role of the inner rehearsal of sentences has been suggested by the linguist Ray Jackendoff. Jackendoff (to appear) suggests that the mental rehearsal of sentences may be the primary means by which our own thoughts are able to become objects of further attention and reflection. The key claim is that linguistic formulation makes complex thoughts available to processes of mental attention, and that this, in turn open them up to a range of further mental operations. It enables us, for example, to pick out different elements of complex thoughts and to scrutinize each in turn. It enables us to "stabilize" very abstract ideas in working memory. And it enables us to inspect and criticize our own reasoning in ways that no other representational modality allows.

What fits internal sentence-based rehearsal to play such an unusual role? The answer, I suggest, must lie in the more mundane (and temporally antecedent) role of language as an instrument of communication. For in order to function as an efficient instrument of communication, public language will have been molded into a code well-suited to the kinds of interpersonal exchange in which ideas are presented, inspected and subsequently critiqued. And this, in turn involves the development of a type of code which minimizes contextuality (most words retain more-or-less the same meaning in the different sentences in which they occur), is effectively modality-neutral (an idea may be prompted by visual, auditory or tactile input and yet be preserved using the same verbal formula), and allows easy rote memorization of simple strings.{7} By "freezing" our own thoughts in the memorable, context-resistant and modality-transcending format of a sentence we thus create a special kind of mental object -- an object which is apt for scrutiny from multiple different cognitive angles, which is not doomed to alter or change every time we are exposed to new inputs or information, and which fixes the ideas at a fairly high level of abstraction from the idiosyncratic details of their proximal origins in sensory input. Such a mental object is, I suggest, ideally suited to figure in the evaluative, critical and tightly focused operations distinction of second order cognition. It is an object fit for the close and repeated inspections highlighted by Jackendoff under the rubric of attending to our own thoughts. The coding system of public language is thus especially apt to be co-opted for more private purposes of inner display, self-inspection and self-criticism, exactly as predicted by the Vygotskian treatments mentioned in Section 1 above. Language stands revealed as a key resource by which we effectively redescribe{8} our own thoughts in a format which makes them available for a variety of new operations and manipulations.

The emergence of such second order cognitive dynamics is plausibly seen as one root of the veritable explosion of types and varieties of external scaffolding structures in human cultural evolution. It is because we can think about our own thinking that we can actively structure our world in ways designed to promote, support and extend our own cognitive achievements. This process also feeds itself, as when the arrival of written text and notation allowed us to begin to fix ever more complex and extended sequences of thought and reason as objects for further scrutiny and attention.

To complete this picture, we should reflect that once the apparatus (internal and external) of sentential and text-based reflection is in place, we may expect the development of new types of non-linguistic thought and encoding -- one's dedicated to the task of managing and interacting with the sentences and texts in more powerful and efficient ways.{9} The linguistic constructions, thus viewed, are a new class of objects which invite us to develop new (non-linguistically based) skills of use, recognition and manipulation. Sentential and non-sentential modes of thought this co-evolve so as to complement, but not replicate, each others special cognitive virtues.

It is a failure to appreciate this deep complementarity that, I suspect, leads Paul Churchland (one of the best and most imaginative neurophilosophers around) to dismiss linguaform expression as just as shallow reflection of our "real" knowledge. Churchland fears that without such marginalization we might mistakenly depict all thought and cognition as involving the unconscious rehearsal of sentence-like symbol strings, and thus be blinded to the powerful, pattern-and-prototype-based encodings which look to be biologically and evolutionarily fundamental. But we have now scouted much fertile intermediate territory.{10} In combining an array of biologically basic pattern-recognition skills with the special `cognitive fixatives' of word and text, we (like the Mangroves) create new landscapes, new fixed points in the sea of thought. Viewed as a complementary cognitive artifact, language can genuinely extend our cognitive horizons -- and without the impossible burden of re-capitulating the detailed contents of non-linguistic thought.




5. Studying the Extended Mind.
Speech and text, we have seen greatly extend the problem-solving capacities of humankind. More profoundly, the practice of putting thoughts into words alters the nature of human experience. Our thoughts become determinate and public objects, apt for rational assessment and for all kinds of meta-cognitive scrutiny. In thus recognizing public language as a powerful transformer of individual computational and experiential space, we invite reflection of a number of further topics. I will end by mentioning just two.

The first concerns the nature of the internal representations that guide human action. A popular image, often associated with Jerry Fodor's reflections on the need for a "language of thought" (e.g., Fodor (1975)(1986)), depicts the internal representational arena as itself a locus of propositionally structured items -- sentences in Mentalese. This image has lately been the subject of a damaging series of criticisms stemming from the successes of non-linguaform computational approaches -- especially those of connectionist (or parallel distributed processing) models. The perspective developed above might, I suspect, encourage us to approach some of these issues in a slightly different way, For the Fodorian view is at least intuitively linked to views of language as essentially a communicative tool. This is because the Fodorian sees linguistic formulations as reasonably faithful reflections of both the contents and the structural forms of internal representations. The view I have been developing is quite different insofar as it depicts the linguistic formulations as importing genuine novelties onto our cognitive horizons. The linguistic formulations are seen as novel both in content and in structure. There is content-novelty insofar as linguistic expression makes new thoughts available by effectively freezing other thoughts as types of static object{12} (images can do this too, but they are not so easily traded in public exchange). And there is structural novelty insofar as the value of the linguistic formulations (especially in written text) partly consists, we saw, in their amenability to a variety of operations and transformations that do not come naturally to the biological brain working in non-linguistic mode. Such novelties, I contend, are not at all predicted by the image of a pre-existing inner code whose basic features and properties are merely recapitulated in our public language formulations. By contrast, they are exactly what would be expected if the public code is not a handy recapitulation of our non-linguistic resources so much as a powerful complement to them.{13}

Such a view suggests a certain gloss on the history and origin of the Fodorian image itself. For perhaps one mistake of classical Artificial Intelligence (upon which the image purports to be based) lay in its mistaking the properties of the linguistically augmented and environmentally extended cognitive agent (the person plus a variety of external representations, especially texts) for the cognitive profile of the basic biological brain. Thus the neat classical separation of data and process and of static symbol structures and CPU may have reflected nothing so much as the gross separation between the biological agent and an external scaffolding of ideas persisting on paper, in filing cabinets and in electronic media.

This notion of the biological agent leads nicely to the second issue I wish to mention. It concerns the question of where the mind ends and the rest of the world begins. Otherwise put, the question concerns how to conceive and locate the boundary between an intelligent system and its world. For certain external (to the biological unit) props and aids may play such a deep role in determining the shape and flow of our thoughts as to invite depiction as part and parcel of the very mechanism of human reason. This depiction is most plausible in the case of the external props of written text and spoken words. For interactions with these external media are ubiquitous (in educated modern cultures), reliable and developmentally basic. Our biologic brains, after learning, expect the presence of text and speech as much as they expect to encounter weight, force, friction and gravity. Language for us is a constant, and as such can be safely relied upon as the backdrop against which on-line processes of neural computation take shape and develop. Just as a neural network controller for moving the arm to a target in space must define its commands to factor in the spring of muscles and the effects of gravity, so the processes of on-board reason may come to factor in the potential contributions of textual off-loading and reorganization, and vocal exchange. The overall cognitive competencies which we identify as mind and intellect may thus be more like ship navigation than capacities of the bare biological brain. Ship navigation (see Hutchins (1995)) is a global emergent from the well-orchestrated adaptation of an extended complex system (comprising individuals, instruments, and practices). Much of what we uncritically identify as our mental capacities may likewise, I suspect, turn out to be properties of the wider, extended systems of which human brains are just one (important) part. In constructing an academic paper, for example, it is common practice to deploy multiple annotated texts, sets of notes and files, plans, lists and more. The writing process often depends heavily on manipulations of these props -- new notes are created, old ones juxtaposed, source materials are wheeled on and off of work surfaces, etc. In giving credit for the final product, however, we often marginalize the special contributions of these external manipulations, and speak as if the biological brain did all the work. No parallel temptation afflicts the person who uses a crane to lift large weights, or a motorized digger to plough trenches! In these cases, it is clear that the person uses additional tools whose capacities extend and complement those of the unaided laborer. The relative invisibility of the special cognitive roles of text and words are a reflection, I think, of their ubiquity and ease of use: a reflection, indeed, of our tendency to think of these operations as proper to the biological agent rather than (like the crane) as technological additions. Perhaps the truth lies midway -- the use of spoken words may be as biologically proper, to the human agent, as the use of webs is to the spider.{15} And the use of written text may thus straddle the intuitive divide between the web (biologically proper) and the crane (a true artifact).

The point, in any case, is that use of words and texts may usefully be seen as computationally complementary to the more primitive and biologically basic kinds of pattern-completing abilities that characterize natural cognition. These complementary operations essentially involve the creation of self -standing structures (short-term ones, like spoken sentences, or long-term ones, like text) that can perform a variety of useful functions such as the sequencing and control of behavior and the freezing of thoughts and ideas into objects for further attention and analysis. The availability of these functions extends the bound of human cognition as surely as the provision of a new board extends the bounds of a personal computer. In particular, it is our capacity to create and operate upon external representations that allows us to use manipulations of the physical environment as integral parts of so many of our problem-solving routines. In thus reaching out to the world we blunt the dividing line between the intelligent system and the world. We create wider computational webs whose understanding and analysis may require us to apply the tools and concepts of cognitive science to larger, hybrid entities comprising brains, bodies and a variety of external structures, traces and processes.

To endorse a notion of computational processes as criss-crossing brain, body and world is not yet to endorse a parallel notion of cognitive or mental processes. Perhaps cognition is all in the head, but computation spreads liberally out into the world. My own inclinations are less conservative. I suspect that our intuitive notions of mind and cognition actually do pick out these larger extended systems and that as a result the biological brain is only one component of the intelligent system we call the mind.{16} But I will settle for a weaker conclusion -- one that merely implicates our linguistic capacities in some highly productive transformations of our overall computational powers. This power of computational transformation constitutes a neglected virtue of linguistic practice. It reveals language as the ultimate upgrade: so ubiquitous it is almost invisible; so intimate, it is not clear whether it is a kind of tool or an added dimension of the user. But whatever the boundaries, we confront a complex coalition in which the basic biological brain is fantastically empowered by some of its strangest and most recent creations: words in the air, symbols on the printed page.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisiblePhencyclidine
Molecule

Registered: 06/02/03
Posts: 2,915
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1704524 - 07/10/03 11:57 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

I disagree.

When I look at my own psychedelic experiences, it was allowing myself to drop the pretense that the experience was somehow beyond words that allowed me to articulate the experiences.

The phenomenon you're referring to, applies to all language. Words only refer to other words.

If I say, "Sex feels somewhat like masturbation." You still can't know what sex feels like for me, no matter how many times you've had sex, and assuming you're the same gender. A drug induced experience is no different. We describe experiences by referring to something else. Thus, I conclude that one is just as able to articulate a psychedelic experience as they are any other experience, such as going for a walk.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisibleZero7a1
Leaving YourWasteland

Registered: 10/23/02
Posts: 3,594
Loc: Passing Cloud
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: Phencyclidine]
    #1704547 - 07/11/03 12:05 AM (20 years, 8 months ago)

you dont think thats limiting though? Cause it screws royally with my head. Its easier just to sit there and try to imagine... than try to come to words. Cause when i try to talk about something subjective... it just goes right out the shitter. I like to make art... to express what i otherwise couldnt express in language. cause for me... a piece whether it "speaks" to someone or not is still filled with an enormous ammount of my own experience... what i project into that piece. i make it what it is. some people make an art of words, which to me is something i again cant rightly say. but as you say,you know,because you refer to the structure of what i say... right?


--------------------
What?

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
InvisiblePhencyclidine
Molecule

Registered: 06/02/03
Posts: 2,915
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: Zero7a1]
    #1706047 - 07/11/03 01:28 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

What I mean is that words either do their job, and can act as approximations or they don't. In the former case, then describing drug trips is no more limited than describing what a bannana looks like. In the latter case, then no information can be accurately transmitted.

In either case, the psychedelic experience does not hold a special status as being ineffable.

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
OfflineStrumpling
Neuronaut
Registered: 10/11/02
Posts: 7,571
Loc: Hyperspace
Last seen: 12 years, 10 months
Re: Limitations of Language [Re: silversoul7]
    #1706893 - 07/11/03 07:08 PM (20 years, 8 months ago)

Here's a related quote from Waking Life:

"Creation seems to come out of imperfection. It seems to come out of a striving and a frustration, and this is where I think language came from. It came from our desire to transcend our isolation and have some sort of connection with one another. And it had to be easy, when it was just simple survival, like you know...water, we came up with a sound for that, or sabre-toothed tiger right behind you!, we came up with a sound for that. But, when it gets really interesting, I think, is when we use that same system of symbols to communicate all the abstract and intangible things that we're experiencing. What is frustration? or what is anger? or love? When I say "love," the sound comes out of my mouth and hits the other person's ear, travels through this Byzantine conduit in their brain, through their memories of love, or lack of love, and they register what I'm saying, and they say "Yes, I understand," but how do I know they understand? Words are inert; They're just symbols; They're dead. You know? And, so much of our experience is intangible. So much of what we perceive cannot be expressed; It's unspeakable. Yet, when we communicate with one another, and we feel that we have connected, and we think that we are understood, I think we have a feeling of almost spiritual communion, and that feeling might be transient, but I think it's what we live for."

I like what she has to say at the end there - I think this is part of the reason so many of us are HERE at the shroomery.... this feeling that we get when we feel we have effectively communicated or understood an idea to/from so many people is indeed very unique and very "holy."


--------------------
Insert an "I think" mentally in front of eveything I say that seems sketchy, because I certainly don't KNOW much. Also; feel free to yell at me.
In addition: SHPONGLE

Extras: Filter Print Post Top
Jump to top Pages: 1

Shop: Kraken Kratom Red Vein Kratom   North Spore North Spore Mushroom Grow Kits & Cultivation Supplies   Bridgetown Botanicals CBD Concentrates   Myyco.com Golden Teacher Liquid Culture For Sale   Original Sensible Seeds Autoflowering Cannabis Seeds   Unfolding Nature Unfolding Nature: Being in the Implicate Order   PhytoExtractum Buy Bali Kratom Powder   MagicBag.co All-In-One Bags That Don't Suck


Similar ThreadsPosterViewsRepliesLast post
* Anyone ever think that english language was a trap?
( 1 2 all )
Droz 3,706 24 07/03/04 06:04 AM
by daba
* The language barrier
( 1 2 all )
Silversoul 3,317 30 02/18/06 01:21 AM
by gettinjiggywithit
* The illusions of language and culture *DELETED* Lion 2,503 16 09/30/13 08:17 PM
by Icelander
* Human Logic, Linguistics and The Mushroom ParabolaChair 3,261 6 04/29/04 05:59 AM
by fireworks_god
* linguistics and telepathy llib 1,224 13 07/17/02 07:30 PM
by Swami
* DNA Language Discoveries.- VERY interesting!
( 1 2 3 all )
gettinjiggywithit 4,901 45 09/27/04 03:27 PM
by 3eyes
* Does language limit our imagination?
( 1 2 all )
Revelation 2,573 29 12/24/02 09:54 AM
by spud
* pre-language
( 1 2 all )
plexus 2,773 35 08/06/04 12:26 AM
by Mushmonkey

Extra information
You cannot start new topics / You cannot reply to topics
HTML is disabled / BBCode is enabled
Moderator: Middleman, DividedQuantum
2,238 topic views. 2 members, 4 guests and 23 web crawlers are browsing this forum.
[ Show Images Only | Sort by Score | Print Topic ]
Search this thread:

Copyright 1997-2024 Mind Media. Some rights reserved.

Generated in 0.027 seconds spending 0.007 seconds on 14 queries.